Indestructibility properties of remarkable cardinals
Y. Cheng and V. Gitman, “Indestructibility properties of remarkable cardinals,” Arch. Math. Logic, vol. 54, no. 7-8, pp. 961–984, 2015.
Since the seminal results of Levy and Solovay [1] on the indestructibility of large cardinals by small forcing and Laver on the making a supercompact cardinal indestructible by all $\lt\kappa$-directed closed forcing [2], indestructibility properties of various large cardinal notions have been intensively studied. A decade after Laver's result, Gitik and Shelah showed that strong cardinals can be made indestructible by all weakly $\leq\kappa$-closed forcing with the Prikry property [3] (see this post), a class that includes all $\leq\kappa$-closed forcing, and Woodin showed, using his technique of surgery, that they can be made indestructible by forcing of the form ${\rm Add}(\kappa,\theta)$. More recently, Hamkins and Johnstone showed that strongly unfoldable cardinals can be made indestructible by all $\lt\kappa$-closed $\kappa^+$-preserving forcing [4]. It turns out that not all large cardinals possess robust indestructibility properties. Very recently, Bagaria et al. showed that a number of large cardinal notions including superstrong, huge, and rank-into-rank cardinals are superdestructible: they cannot even be indestructible by ${\rm Add}(\kappa,1)$ [5]. In this article, we show that remarkable cardinals have indestructibility properties resembling those of strong cardinals. They can be made indestructible by all $\lt\kappa$-closed $\leq\kappa$-distributive forcing and by all two-step iterations of the form ${\rm Add}(\kappa,\theta)*\dot{\mathbb R}$, where $\dot{\mathbb R}$ is forced to be $\lt\kappa$-closed and $\leq\kappa$-distributive.
Theorem: If $\kappa$ is remarkable, then there is a forcing extension in which the remarkability of $\kappa$ is becomes indestructible by all $\lt\kappa$-closed $\leq\kappa$-distributive forcing and by all two-step iterations ${\rm Add}(\kappa,\theta)*\dot{\mathbb R}$, where $\dot{\mathbb R}$ is forced to be $\lt\kappa$-closed and $\leq\kappa$-distributive.
In particular, a remarkable $\kappa$ can be made indestructible by all $\leq\kappa$-closed forcing, and since $\dot {\mathbb R}$ can be trivial, by all forcing of the form ${\rm Add}(\kappa,\theta)$. One application of the main theorem is that any ${\rm GCH}$ pattern can be forced above a remarkable cardinal. Another application uses a recent forcing construction of Cheng, Hamkins, and Friedman [6], to produce a remarkable cardinal that is not remarkable in ${\rm HOD}$. Using techniques from the proof the main theorem, we also show that remarkability is preserved by the canonical forcing of the ${\rm GCH}$.
For the indestructibility arguments, we define the notion of a remarkable Laver function and show that every remarkable cardinal carries such a function. Although Laver-like functions can be forced to exist for many large cardinal notions [7], remarkable cardinals along with supercompact and strong cardinals are some of the few that outright possess such fully set-anticipating functions. For instance, not every strongly unfoldable cardinal has a Laver-like function because it is consistent that $\diamondsuit_\kappa({\rm REG})$ fails at a strongly unfoldable cardinal [8].
Definition: A cardinal $\kappa$ is remarkable if in the ${\rm Coll}(\omega,\lt\kappa)$ forcing extension $V[G]$, for every regular cardinal $\lambda>\kappa$, there is a $V$-regular cardinal $\overline\lambda<\kappa$ and $j:H_{\overline\lambda}^V\to H_\lambda^V$ with critical point $\gamma$ such that $j(\gamma)=\kappa$.
Schindler originally used a different primary characterization of remarkable cardinals, but he has recently switched to using the above characterization, which gives remarkable cardinals a character of generic supercompactness [9]. Magidor showed that $\kappa$ is supercompact if and only if for every regular cardinal $\lambda>\kappa$, there is a regular cardinal $\overline \lambda<\kappa$ and $j:H_{\overline\lambda}\to H_\lambda$ with critical point $\gamma$ such $j(\gamma)=\kappa$ [10].
Schindler introduced remarkable cardinals when he isolated them as the large cardinal notion whose existence is equiconsistent with the assertion that the theory of $L(\mathbb R)$ cannot be altered by proper forcing. The assertion that the theory of $L(\mathbb R)$ is absolute for all set forcing is intimately connected with ${\rm AD}^{L(\mathbb R)}$ and its consistency strength lies in the neighborhood of infinitely many Woodin cardinals [11]. In contrast, remarkable cardinals are much weaker than measurable cardinals, and indeed they can exist in $L$. Consistency-wise, they fit tightly into the $\alpha$-iterable hierarchy of large cardinal notions (below a Ramsey cardinal) introduced by Gitman and Welch [12], where they lie above 1-iterable, but below 2-iterable cardinals, placing them above hierarchies of ineffability, but much below an $\omega$-Erdős cardinal. Remarkable cardinals are also totally indescribable and $\Sigma_2$-reflecting. Strong cardinals are remarkable, but the least measurable cardinal cannot be remarkable by $\Sigma_2$-reflection. For more background to remarkable cardinals, see this post.
References
- A. Lévy and R. M. Solovay, “Measurable cardinals and the continuum hypothesis,” Israel J. Math., vol. 5, pp. 234–248, 1967.
- R. Laver, “Making the supercompactness of $κ$ indestructible under $κ$-directed closed forcing,” Israel J. Math., vol. 29, no. 4, pp. 385–388, 1978.
- M. Gitik and S. Shelah, “On certain indestructibility of strong cardinals and a question of Hajnal,” Arch. Math. Logic, vol. 28, no. 1, pp. 35–42, 1989.
- J. D. Hamkins and T. A. Johnstone, “Indestructible strong unfoldability,” Notre Dame J. Form. Log., vol. 51, no. 3, pp. 291–321, 2010.
- J. Bagaria, J. D. Hamkins, K. Tsaprounis, and T. Usuba, “Superstrong and other large cardinals are never Laver indestructible,” Arch. Math. Logic, vol. 55, no. 1-2, pp. 19–35, 2016.
- Y. Cheng, S.-D. Friedman, and J. D. Hamkins, “Large cardinals need not be large in HOD,” Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, vol. 166, no. 11, pp. 1186–1198, 2015.
- J. D. Hamkins, “A class of strong diamond principles,” Manuscript, 2002.
- Dz̆amonja Mirna and J. D. Hamkins, “Diamond (on the regulars) can fail at any strongly unfoldable cardinal,” Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, vol. 144, no. 1-3, pp. 83–95, Dec. 2006.
- R. Schindler, “Remarkable cardinals,” in Infinity, computability, and metamathematics, vol. 23, Coll. Publ., London, 2014, pp. 299–308.
- M. Magidor, “On the role of supercompact and extendible cardinals in logic,” Israel J. Math., vol. 10, pp. 147–157, 1971.
- R.-D. Schindler, “Proper forcing and remarkable cardinals,” Bull. Symbolic Logic, vol. 6, no. 2, pp. 176–184, 2000.
- V. Gitman and P. D. Welch, “Ramsey-like cardinals II,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 76, no. 2, pp. 541–560, 2011.